Meinecke Notes Hitlers example essay topic

3,137 words
How Convincing Do You Find Meineckes Explanation For The Rise Of National Socialism As a historian, I appreciate the absurdity of the rise of Nazism, however I have found Meineckes explanation of the rise of Nazism, given its date of publication, to be not so much a disclaimer on behalf of the German people, as others have found it to be, but almost an attempt at academic vindication of the Anglo-American post-war view of Germany, often supported by uncheckable sources. Before assessing the books contents, it is important to note certain noteworthy events surrounding the books publication that require attention. Meineckes book was produced in 1946 and published with the aid of Edward Y. Hartshorne, an American working in the reconstruction of the German university system. Given the nature of the time, and the means by which Meinecke found a publisher, one would expect a stance on Nazism that would be helpful to the American occupation. What appear to be numerous anglicisms do appear throughout the volume, possibly suggesting that Meinecke had been priming himself on English texts (the use of the present participle in grundstuerzende Revolution is not a common German usage). Meinecke, soon to accept the rectorship of the Free University of Berlin, an institute founded with the blessing of General Clay himself, would certainly have quite an incentive for in objectivity as the foremost western scholar on the Cold Wars front line.

The introduction to the book also provides an important insight into Meineckes life during the period. Meinecke says that he was durch ein Augen leiden behind ert and had to rely fast auf mein Gedaechtnis. He notes that the book should not only be read as the product of a handicapped author but as just one part of the picture, and that the boo was not only answering the questions it posed itself, but also acting as a medium for recording phrases, quotes and sayings of prominent persons of the era which might otherwise be lost. The desire to use certain of these sources might have also shaped his argument to some extent. Meinecke ends his introduction with a wish that his book might help the rebuilding process and that the new Germany could be spiritually purer. This moralizing is just one of a series of reasons to be sceptical about the books contents, as it suggests that Meinecke is attempting to tell the Nazi story as a cautionary tale and not as a pure history.

Meinecke starts by identifying the two great movements of the nineteenth century as nationalism (which became imperialism) and socialism. Nationalism was the product of an end to the way of life aimed solely at the advancement and enrichment of ones own individuality and was bourgeois in nature. The nationalist movements were born of the liberal movements that succeeded in securing the liberties of so many nations by the means of constitutions or democracies. Meinecke notes that during the Revolution of 1848, the needs of the revolting faction were not so much liberty, as power, as their liberties had apparently already been secured.

Meanwhile, the masses created by industrialisation pushed for socialism so as to safeguard fully their standard of living. Meinecke sees the two great waves of the nineteenth century [as having] a wholly peculiar character in Germany where they developed fighting qualities which, when at the historic moment arrived for their intermingling were to be fatal. Meinecke sees the vying between these powers as the first phases in the degeneration of the German middle classes. The hardening of nationalism that lead to the preponderance of such groups as the Pan-Germans, and a widened divide between the socialists and nationalists (which, in turn led to Naumann's national socialist movement).

The combat of the ideologies, as it later would in Weimar, led to a spiritual and cultural renaissance, second only to the Goethe zeit. At the same time, however, amoral nihilist nationalism which viewed a nation as not only superior, but in demand of superior scales of morality and humanity would set the stage for the hypocrisy of the Nazi state. This analysis would seem to be an over-complication of the emergence of the Pan-German movements. In an era when ethnic groups were still classed as different species, and when it was believed races carried moral and cognitive characteristics, it is unsurprising that a number of pseudo-scientific eugenic theories about who the greatest and aboriginal race were (the Aryans) were produced.

Given the number of German cultural icons in the era, the emergence of the German economic and military power, Germans cultural force it is not surprising that many papers concluding a German superiority were produced with scientific backing. The nineteenth century Germans can be forgiven for making rash assumptions about the nature race in an age of ignorance in an attempt at scientific endeavour. Meinecke, however, feels the need to exonerate the German people of the Holocaust, which he does by attributing German anti-Semitism not to Nazism but to a general trend. This dehumanization of German society is a theme of Meineckes book, as he notes that causality is more complicated than simple events leading to one another, and that a sweep of events can be as important as an individual person or action. This view of the movement of history with semi-static figures diverting its flow diminishes personal responsibility and was probably a tactful way of documenting the rise of Nazism in Germany immediately after the war, although it lacks precision and the scientific cut that most historians pride themselves on.

According to Meineckes account, at the outbreak of the First World War, the fragmented German people were united behind the Kaiser reich and social, economic and political divides were momentarily dissolved in a flurry of Germanism hope. However, Meinecke writes, as early as 1915, one could perceive that the August synthesis would not last. The demands of the worker for full equality of legal rights now that he had shown in the fight for the Fatherland that his contribution was as valuable as that of any other citizen were at odds with the burge rliche Mittel stand, and soon the countrys fragile social truce fell apart. In the autumn of 1917, the democratic parties formed the Peoples League whilst the Fatherland Party was formed to oppose their progressive stance, and were able to more forcefully act upon the weak Imperial government. The influence of the Pan-Germans over the Fatherland Party was almost absolute, and their refusal to bow down to inferior peoples apparently prevented a peace accord being reached earlier. Meinecke asks the reader can one doubt any longer that the Pan-Germans and the Fatherland party are an exact prelude to Hitlers rise to power That the German people were swept along by euphoria is beyond doubt.

The famous pictures of the crowds, including Hitler, at the Odeonsplatz and Marienplatz in Munich are celebrated icons of war, and the rejoicing Bavarians were the most un Prussian element in German society. However, that the country was united and behind the war effort is dubious. The precepts of socialism did not change. The socialist groupings were as anti-imperialist as they had been before. Although they would not condemn a war with such popular support, especially one marketed as being in self-defence by the Imperial Government, they would have been tactful in their disdain for the war. The influence of the Pan-Germans was more evident in the Ludendorff's role.

Ludendorff, the most celebrated of the Beer hall Putsches, was one of the two generals who, by 1918 had control over the civil authorities and were essentially running a Prussian Army autocracy across Germany. The role of the Kaiser, and thus, the Fatherland Party, had been minimal ised by the two Field Marshals who held the balance of power. The Fatherland Party was, at best, a sideline interest group. Their failure to attract sufficient support to survive in the Weimar Republic is perhaps indicative of their interest. Meinecke perceives the next phase in the rise of Nazism as the Dolchstosslegende.

The growth of the belief in the military failures causation by revolution on the home front was widespread on the right. The blaming of the Peoples League, who went on to form the parties of the Weimar Republic, for the defeat, which descended to the murder of Rathenau in 1922 as payment for his signature on the Treaty of Versailles, would mean that the conservative upper middle class and the aristocracy were sworn to destroy the Republic by whatever means were necessary. Meinecke notes that a friend, Siegfried vs. Karloff, once said that the Weimar Constitution was destroyed over the card table. He notes that the Jewish community was too greedy in their lifestyles and that the inevitable jealousy, spurred by the Pan-Germans, led to a strong anti-Semitic tendency. The post-war worlds first revolution occurred in 1922, when Mussolini marched on Rome and seized power, and Meinecke says that it was in a way that the German people wished to emulate. Wishing to mobilise the little Reichswehr and the Freikorps against the Republic, the conservative right knew that, excluding the commander in chief himself, General vs. See ckt, the Reichswehr was still a Wilhelmine construction with Wilhelmine leanings and was still dominated by Prussian militarism.

My greatest difficulty with any single aspect of Meineckes explanation comes in the chapter Homo Sapiens and Homo Faber. His explanation of the degeneration of the Weimar Germans into Nazi Germans is explained away in a series of occasionally unsupported and deeply subjective generalisations. The relationship between the rational and the irrational seems to be an over-complication of the concept of emotive motivation as opposed to logical-rational motivation, of which people, individually and as a society, need a healthy balance. The next section of the chapter, however seems to be unsupported conjecture at best. Quoting a mysterious observer, Meinecke claims that an intense classical education can lead to radicalism later in life when the person matures into political awareness, due to a lack of understanding.

This means that the burgeoning class of engineers and technicians created by the industrialisation process was a potential time-bomb. Evidently using Mein Kampf as his source about Hitlers time in Vienna, Meinecke, who admittedly lacked the resources of the late twentieth century about the era, used Hitler as an example of someone lacking classical education who had worked in an intensive manner. Hitler had, at the least, initially a classical education and the fact that he never worked on a construction site, let alone made political theories based on his experiences in one. The (Marxist) idea that mankind's fundamental state has only ever been changed by industrialisation is expressed in a new way in Meineckes text. He claims that technology had catalyzed the formation of this explosive new class.

The idea that industrial Germany had a new class of disciplined and eager people whose concentration had been honed by mundane and repetitive jobs, and yet whose cognitive ability could easily be sparked and harnessed by fashionable ideas seems a little too far a generalisation. The next phase in Meineckes assessment of the rise of the Nazis comes again to the Prussian militarism. He paraphrases Voltaires maxim that most states keep an army yet in Prussia, the army keeps a state. Prussian army had gone from a Grande Armee style state-dominating force under Friedrich Wilhelm I, to a militia supplemented elite, then back to an elite medium that had dominated continental politics for 40 years upto the First World War. The ever-adapting Prussian army held only a few principles dear. The Teutonic subservience to ones lord and the willingness to sacrifice ones life for another goal made the Prussian mindset, whatever form the Prussians assumed on the field.

This narrow-mindedness was blamed for the failure of the Schlieffen Plan. Claiming that a homo faber obsessed with railway tracks and guns and overlooked the political consequences of the invasion of Belgium drew up the plan, Meinecke stretches the distinction between the professional man and the renaissance man even further. This rationality and un emotiveness of this mindset saw Hitler as a potential channel not only for reversal of the Dolchstosslegende but also as a source of energy and power for a German risorgimento. The prosecution of young officers at Ulm is proof of the susceptibility of this social class to Hitlerian propaganda. Although the inclusion of the homo faber principle is still contentious for me, the idea of Hitler appealing to the German army is quite plausible, and one I would support.

I do not agree that the army was important as it held the balance of power in the Republic. As Meinecke says, the President absorbed as much from the army as the army took from him, and a lack of army support was one of the issues that unseated Bruning. Meinecke goes on to briefly map the power of the appeal of Nazism to the German youth and war veterans. Again, the Dolchstosslegende but also the promise of Arbeit und Boot attracted the youth. Allegedly, Hitler came to power through a dazzled youth movement which built the SA and SS into a powerful force to rival the Reichswehr.

On the collapse of the Grand Coalition, and of the Bruning Coalition, Hindenburg hearkened to the calls of the Army, and sent for the man he had once described as a Jumped-up Bohemian Corporal to become Chancellor. I believe that the power of the SA and SS was over emphasised in Meineckes account and that Hitler did not come to power through the SA and SS, but, by 1933, in spite of it. Meinecke goes on to state that he and colleagues (including Groener) were discussing the flood of Nazism, and its rise. The claims that Groener would not be able to stop it are of interest. Although the near-blind professor admitted that he was unable to read his notes, this seems a highly unlikely thing for Groener to say. In the words of Karl Dietrich Brac her, the history of National Socialism was the history of its fatal underestimation.

Had anyone in the Cabinet of Barons or the Grand Coalition suspected that the Nazis were a dominant and growing force, then it seems unlikely that von Papen would have claimed that he would appoint Hitler and push him so hard into a corner that hell squeak. That Kurt von Schleicher wished to crush Nazism is also highly unlikely. The man who attempted to use the Strasser bloc of the party as a separate bloc would surely not have tried to destroy it. Meinecke continues his summary of the rise of Nazism by questioning the role of Bismarcks legacy of Machiavellianism. Although acknowledging the Empire as an achievement of historic greatness and acknowledging it as a precious memory, Meinecke claims that the empire ceded too much to the militarist instincts of its founder and that Bismarcks use of the militarist instinct was all that people identified as his gift to Germany but that his real legacy was noteworthy for his shrewd and circumspect manipulation of the Prussian instinct. Indeed, the pro-Bismarck Meinecke passes over the Kulturkampf hurriedly as he rushes to exonerate the greatest of the German statesmen.

Although I would agree that Bismarck was a great statesman and that his legacy was of militarism, I would not say that it was a unique legacy, but one that he was himself left by the eighteenth century kings of Prussia. I would also reckon that the Prussian militarism is overstated by Meinecke. In chapter eight Meinecke clarifies his theories about chance and general tendencies. Meinecke expresses the rather vague, if accurate, view that general tendency, trends and patterns can be interfered with by individuals, but that sometimes individuals are swept along with the tide of history.

Meinecke notes Hitlers prescribed aims as being the reversal of Versailles, a solution to the Jewish question and an end to the depression. The power of these three ideas (and the spectre of communism) in appealing to the electorate, is powerful indeed, although the anti-Semitic aspect should probably not rank with the other three factors in its provenance. The chance that Hitler was given these axes to grind and a demagogic power so intense brought him electoral power. Meinecke notes other instances of chance working for Hitler.

The election of Hugenberg to the leadership of the D NVP in June 1930 was won by chance as some opponents of his were not there to cast their votes votes which would have lost Hugenberg the election. The election allowed the formation of the National Opposition (to the Young Plan) and then the formal Harz burg Front of October 1931. This gave Hitler a majority in parliament in 1933, but had Hugenberg opponents turned up so much could have been different. Hitlers appointment is another chance in Meineckes eyes. The un-needed appointment which followed no trend or pattern was the result, in Meineckes eyes, of von Hindenburg's weakness. His inability to deal with his son, Schleicher, Muller, Papen and Bruning is hardly a weakness so much as a lack of strength.

Meinecke notes the successes in reversing Versailles, in rebuilding the economy, in securing allied support for an increased military, in setting up rival youth groups to the Hitler Youth and in the elections of November 1932 which were much reduced on their previous standing. The general trend (despite the result of the elections in Lippe-Detmold) was against the Nazis, and Meinecke is probably right in agreeing with Julius Strasser who believed that Hitler had missed the boat in January 1933 and that the Nazis were on the way to obscurity like the DDP before them... Meinecke attributes the final trigger of the Deutsche Kata strophe to Hindenberg's weak character and his inability to stand up for the Weimar Republic, as have so many other historians. This is a conclusion which I accept. However, the growth of the homo faber class, the primacy of militarism, the end of the reasonable human nature and the view that Nazism was not a specifically German event, yet was apparently born of German characteristics in Germany and nowhere else I do not accept.