Response Able To The Existential Predicament example essay topic

2,184 words
Concepts of pathology, as treated by the traditions of clinical psychology and psychiatry, define what is normal and abnormal in human behaviour. Various psychological paradigms exist today, each emphasising diverse ways of defining and treating psyopathology. Most commonly utilised is the medical model which is limited in many respects, criticised for reducing patients problems to a list of pathological symptoms that have a primarily biological base and which are to be treated behaviorally or pharmacologic ally (Schwartz & Wiggins 1999). Such reductionist ic positivist ways of viewing the individual maintain the medical discourse of borderline personality, schizoid, paranoid or clinically depressed, often failing to address the wider socio- l tural environment of the individual. Pilgrim (1992) suggests that such diagnostic pidgeon-holing does not enhance humanity, nor aid those who are dealing with the distressed individual to find meaning.

It also neglects to consider life beyond the physical, failing to address the more philosophical questions that abound from our very existence. Existential psychiatry and psychology arose in Europe in the 1940's and 1950's as a direct response to the dissatisfaction with prevailing efforts to gain scientific understanding in psychiatry (Binswanger 1963). Existentialism is the title of a set of philosophical ideas that emphasise the existence of the human being, the lack of meaning and purpose in life and the solitude of human existence. Existentialism stresses the jeopardy of life, the void ness of human reality and admits that the human being thrown into the world, a world in which pain, frustration, sickness, contempt, malaise and death dominates (Barnes 1962).

How one positions oneself in that world becomes the focus for existential notions of pathology, a responsibility that is present for every human being not one confined to the mentally ill. In this sense the human being is response-able to the existential predicament that is life and the necessary struggles that arise through negotiating these conditions in every lived moment. In this essay I will give a brief outline of the history of existential thinkers, then discuss how the existential challenge emphasises one's freedom of choice of being-in-the-world and how ultimately one must take responsibility for how one reacts to the givens of existence. I will outline how these predicaments of life can precipitate anxiety, guilt, inertia and the loss of will; that facing the responsibilities to the givens and choices in existence can cause ontological anxiety, a natural reaction to living authentically, and the problems incurred when one avoids tackling these predicaments and contradictions, thus living in authentically or choosing to withdraw into a solitary world.

The existential notion of pathology will be contrasted with that of the positivist approach. During the Second World War existentialism found it's zenith of popularity, a time when Europe was in crisis, faced with mass death and destruction. Existentialism provides a moving account of the agony of being thrown into the world, perhaps appealing the times of intense confusion, despair and rootlessness caused by the War and it's aftermath. In the 19th century existential thought is found in the writings of Soren Kierkegaard (1813-1855), Friedrich Neitzche (1844-1900), Fyodor Dostoyevski (1821-1881) and later Jean-Paul Satre (1905-1980), all of whom were opposed to the predominant philosophies, and scientific dogmas, of their time and committed to exploring the experience of reality in a passionate and personal manner.

The birth of modern existentialism can be attributed to Martin Heidegger (1889-1976), who's thinking was applied to psychiatry, psychotherapy and psychoanalysis by Karl Jaspers (1883-1969), Ludwig Binswanger (1881-1966) and Me dard Boss (1903-1990). The movement attempted to gain a sense of the subjective phenomena of mental illness using existential concepts (Owen 1994). In America psychotherapists May and Yalom (1984) formulated their unique type of existential psychotherapy, as did Frankl (1963) in Austria th logo therapy, and also Laing (1960), working with schizophrenics, in the anti-psychiatry movement in Britain. Ironically many of the writers celebrated as existentialists deny to be grouped together as one school of thought, agreeing wholly on all concepts, thus a diverse collection of tenets are represented under the umbrella of existentialism. Arising from a deeply philosophical root of ideas existentialism explores the experience of existence, asking what does it mean to be in this world. Concerned with ontology, rather than aetiology, existential theorists avoid models that categorise individuals, seeking to uncover that which is universal in the human dilemma (Deurzen-Smith 1996).

Scientific enquiry fails to procure a complete worldview of human-being by pertaining to unexamined assumptions (Jaspers 1963). Human-being is revealed in the workings of guilt, conflict, psychosis, suffering and death. Only by facing up to these contingencies can humanity be accomplished. Bugental (1978) defines identity as a process, not a fixidity, and when one realises this one is faced with the nothingness of being. This nothingness, the non-existence of an essence of being, is the primary source of freedom that one must face in each and every moment. Kierkegaard (1944) theories that such freedom brings about existential anxiety through the contemplation of choice and the realisation that one's destiny is not fixed but open to an infinitude of possibilities.

Existential anxiety differs fundamentally from psychological anxiety such that it may have no immediately perceivable cause, it seems irrational, pervades one's whole being, may manifest as an unexplainable dread and arise only in moments when normal insecurities disappear. Yalom (1989) describes it as that which whirr's continuously just beneath the membrane of life, coming to light perhaps through personal crisis, a work of art, or a sermon. May & Yalom (1984) define this anxiety as pertaining to the threat to one's very existence or to values that are identified with existence. Thus there is no cure for such angst, it is argued, for it is an intrinsic component of the human predicament. Both the Freudian and the existential paradigm position anxiety as the central dynamic for psychopathology. Conscious and unconscious ways of dealing with this anxiety are formed, the important distinction is that whereas Freudian anxiety is drive based existential anxiety arises through awareness (May and Yalom 1984).

Existential anxiety manifests differently depending upon the individual's stance toward living; work that is commonly undertaken in the process of existential psychotherapy. It can be utilised as a source of great creativity and energy (May 1969) or reveal itself as neurotic anxiety (May & Yalom 1984), paralyzing the individual. The common notion of mental health being an existence free from anxiety is thus considered absurd. Mental health is attributed to those who are able to live, as much as possible without neurotic, inhibitory anxieties but with the openness and understanding to suffer the inescapable existential anxiety of living. Psychological disturbance, it is argued, comes about when one fails to acknowledge such inherent anxiety, striving to avoid such truth, the consequence of which is inauthentic living (Laing 1960). The gift of existential freedom, is not only the source of anxiety, but brings the burden of profound responsibility.

If it is true that our being is actually nothing and that we are in a constant flux, then one is faced with a terrible emptiness and at the same time a miraculous freedom (Bugental 1978). May (1989) observes that freedom is how we relate to our destiny and destiny is significant only because we have freedom. One must take this freedom of being and the responsibility that goes with it, including the guilt of one's actions. Each action negates the other possible course of actions and their consequences, so that one must be accountable without excuse. As human beings are not fixed in this world, such as things are, one is free to realise one's aims, to materialise one's dreams and forge one's own destiny (Owen 1994).

The person who lives in this manner is living authentically, or in Satre's (1951) terminal y good faith. Consequently psychological disturbance, or pathology, is the negation of this process of authenticity - inauthentic living or bad faith, in which one moves away from the burden of responsibility, through belief in dogmas, regarding on ese as subject to outside influences, conforming to standards or roles and assuming that actions are predetermined. Kierkergaard (1954) argues that society constantly denies the reality of nothingness and it's inherent implications for living. Such inauthentic living is a world of self deception, for one has refused to take the challenge of responsibility and confront the anxiety that comes with such freedom. May (1969) addresses the issue of will, arguing against Freudian notions of determinism, as the point where one acts on one's freedom. He highlights the crisis of will in the modern Western world.

May (1969) presents a vignette, of a catatonic episode in a patient who had experienced a crisis of will and values, whereby he had become so acutely aware of his responsibility and actions that no movement was possible for fear of negative omnipotent consequences. In his pathological world he was caught an inner dead-lock. This case is likened to the general stupor of an apathetic society in which individuals have chosen to allow others to make their decisions, relinquishing the responsibility for their destinies, unable to make the decisions that mig carry out their wishes, leading to the paralysis of will. As Laing (1960) puts it in a hell of frenetic passivity. We inhabit a modern world which promotes personal power and independence and yet our predicament is that the majority of human beings renounce their responsibility to will and choice, choosing to live in a culture of blame and discontent. We have the choice to choose, or not to choose, in Shakespeare's words, To be or not to be.

Laing (1960) observes that some individuals do actually make the choice of withdrawing from the world of relatedness completely into their own self-made worlds. This he observed with schizophrenics when the environment, often the family, was experienced as too hostile and destructive, causing the individual to retreat into a safer inner world. Schizophrenia, he posits, is a strategy invented in order to live in an unlive able world. Frankl (1963) observed this in the Nazi concentration camps - those who had schizoid tendencies were able to survive the harsh conditions better than those in touch with an inner reality and the outer world. May (1969) has pointed towards this notion too in observing that those astro naughts best suited for space travel were a e to withdraw partially into their own schizoid worlds. In this sense the existential approach to such phenomena as schizophrenia emphasises the importance of the subjectivity of experience for the patient, breaking away from stigmatising labels and objectifying forms of therapy and allowing the individual to journey through their authentic experience of madness (Deurzen-Smith 1984).

Deurzen-Smith (1996) defines psychological disturbance not as that which is confined to the traditionally perceived mentally ill but a natural occurrence of the struggle, that each one of us must engage in, with the disturbing givens in life. Problems are therefore, are not seen as obstructions to psychological health but as challenges that must be risen to. In life it is certain that we will be confronted with new situations that challenge and undermine our evasions of the human paradox. Unexpected even, such as the death of a loved one, may expose one's vulnerability and sense of false security in a self-deceived world. Boredom also might precipitate such an existential crisis. Critics of the existential approach site that it is too academic and intellectual, having no practical application in the clinical setting It is often downplayed as not being empirical enough, lacking a psychotherapeutic modality that is set with techniques and interventions (Davison & Neale 1998).

Craib (1992) argues that diagnostic categories are needed in order to approach the necessary level of working knowledge of a client's world. Pilgrim (1992) responds that the positivist categories of pathology are inherently power-laden, demeaning and stigmatising. As C.S. Lewis (1943) noted, We reduce things to mere Nature in order that we may conquer them. When the things are people and their existential status is reduced to a natural category of illness, the same logic of domination applies. Existentialism may not offer a how to approach to the problems of living but rather a lens through which to consider each person in their world. Existential views on pathology may not give evidence of a scientific paradigm but it can offer the science of psychopathology roots much deeper and more significant to the human dilemma than other paradigms that seek mere quantification of mental illnesses.

It offers a phenomenological approach to pathology, not a separation of id and ego, a reduction to pharmacological origins or recognition of maladaptive behaviours, but a holistic view of the entire being in the here and now.

Bibliography

Barnes, H.E. (1962).
Humanistic Existentialism and Contemporary Psychoanalysis, in Kern, E. (ed.) A Collection of Critical Essays. Englewood Cliffs, N. J: Prentice-Hall Binswanger, L. (1963).
Being-in-the-World: Selected papers of Ludwig Binswanger. (trans. J. Need am). New York: Basic Books Bugental, J.F.T. (1978).
Psychotherapy and Process: The Fundamentals of an Existential-Humanistic Approach. Massachusetts: Addison-Wesley Craib, I. (1992).
A response to, Psychotherapy and Political Evasions. In Dryden, W. & Feltham, C. (Eds.) Psychotherapy and It's Discontents. Buckingham: Open University Press Davison, G.C. & Neale, J.M. (1998).
Abnormal Psychology (7th Edition). New York: Wiley Deurzen-Smith, E. (1984).
Existential Therapy. In Dryden, W. (ed. ), Individual Therapy in Britain. Harper & Row: London Deurzen-Smith, E. (1996).
Existential Therapy. In Dryden, W. (ed. ), Handbook of Individual Therapy. London: Sage Frankl, V.E. (1963).
Man's Search for Meaning. London: Hodder & Stoughton Jaspers, K. (1963).
General Psychopathology. (Trans. Hennig, J. & Hamilton M.W. Hamilton). Manchester: Manchester University Press Kierkegaard, S. (1944).
The Concept of Dread (Trans. W. Lowrie). Princeton: Princeton University Press Kierkergaard, S. (1954).
Fear and Trembling and Sickness unto Death. (Trans. W. Lowrie). Princeton: Princeton University Press Laing, R.D. (1960).
The Divided Self. Harmondsworth: Penguin Lewis, C.S. (1943).
The Abolition of Man. Oxford: Oxford University Press May, R. (1969).
Love and Will. New York: Norton. May, R. & Yalom, I. (1984).
Existential Psychotherapy. In C orsini, R.J. (ed. ), Current Psychotherapies. Itasca Illinois: Peacock Owen, I.R. (1994).
Introducing an existential-phenomenological approach: basic phenomenological theory and research- Part 1. Counselling Psychology Quarterly, 7, (3) 261-273 Pilgrim, D. (1992).
Psychotherapy and Political Evasions. Buckingham: Open University Press Satre, J.P. (1951).
Being and Nothingness. (Trans. H. Barnes) Methuen: London Schwartz, M.A. & Wiggins, O.P. (1999).
The Crisis of Present-Day Psychiatry: Regaining the Personal. Psychiatric Times, 16, 9. Yalom, I. (1989).