Socrates Sets Meno example essay topic
Meno, a prominent Thessalian who is visiting Athens, is a member of this class. Meno's semi-foreign status aids Socrates (and Plato) in the dialogue, allowing for eyewitness accounts that Socrates himself could not give. Thus, Meno is able to say with authority that the Thessalians do not have anyone who can clearly teach virtue, while Socrates (and Anytus, a prominent Athenian statesman) can vouch for the sorry state of affairs in Athens. Meno is also a handy interlocutor for this dialogue because he is a follower of Gorgias, one of the most reputable of the Sophist teachers, and knows the Thessalian Sophist community to some extent.
He therefore serves as a Sophist foil for Socrates' logical points. This is not quite a fair fight, of course, since Plato can put whatever words he wants in Meno's mouth, and because Meno is not himself an accomplished Sophist (like Gorgias, who is the central figure in a much lengthier Platonic dialogue). Nonetheless, Socrates sets Meno up early on as a naive believer in the kind of pompous, elaborately rhetorical, but largely vacuous Sophist method of philosophy that had come to prominence some forty or fifty years earlier. Meno readily admits to being an enthusiastic follower of Gorgias and implicitly agrees to Socrates' characterization of Sophist arguments as bold, grand, and presumptuous. In this sense, Meno is something of a straw man set up by Plato to highlight the kind of philosophy Socrates wants to denounce. Meno clearly prefers the Sophist-style definition of color offered by Socrates to the plain, direct definition of shape that Socrates himself prefers.
If Meno is something of a dummy for aristocratic Sophist sympathizers, Anytus is even more clearly a stand-in for the somber, unconsidered values of the Athenian political elite. An actual historical politician of the time, he's grumpy, largely closed to new ideas, and insistent on inherited, class-based customs as the vehicle for virtue -- he suggests that any 'gentleman' on the streets of Athens is a fine example of virtue. Anytus, an Athenian conservative, despises the Sophists. Like other prominent Athenians at the time, he is probably suspicious of the Sophists' cleverness with words and their tendency to lead young followers away from success in worldly matters. Socrates encounters this idea that philosophy is a corrupting influence in many of his dialogues, and that perception will eventually lead to his trial and execution for 'corrupting the youth. ' Thus, Plato is all the more determined to highlight Socrates' profound differences from the Sophists.
We should note briefly the basic form of the Platonic dialogues: Plato, Socrates's tude nt, has written a kind of play, re-enacting the way in which Socrates practiced his philosophy (he did not write it down, but simply argued on the streets). In reading the summary contained on this site, it may not always be clear that Socrates is constantly asking questions of Meno, and only rarely offering points himself. The basic form of this kind of Socratic interview (the elenchus) is for Socrates to get his interviewee to admit to Socrates' points in response to questions (although, in practical terms, these answers are often just affirmations of what Socrates puts forth). This method is deeply related to the idea of anamnesis -- the interlocutors are thought to be actually 'recalling' the truths set out in the dialogues, rather than simply learning them from Socrates. The examination of Meno's slave is an excellent microcosm of this process. If Plato's dialogues in general are notable for their depth within a relatively straightforward framework, the Meno is particularly so.
At first glance, the dialogue seems to proceed quite clearly (albeit with a few somewhat involuted sections, such as the geometrical quiz given to Meno's slave). It also seems to settle or establish very little -- in the end, no definitive answer is given to the text's central question of what virtue is. This simplicity and inconclusiveness, however, hide an extremely ambitious set of goals. The first such project we encounter concerns the nature of a definition, a concept quite new in Socrates' time and largely at odds with the received wisdom of ordinary Greek citizens. That the nature of virtue could even be a question is remarkable to Meno (and presumably to Plato's early readers) -- indeed, he opens the dialogue not by asking what virtue is, but rather if and how virtue can be taught. Thus, much of the initial dialogue is devoted to the idea that virtue must be rigorously defined before we can deal with subsequent questions about it.
This point is at the heart of the Socratic elenchus, which seeks to clear the ground of received, unconsidered knowledge in favor of the pursuit of truth. Meno confidently offers a number of definitions of virtue, but each of them merely cobbles together various aspects of Greek cultural custom. Socrates then dissects these to show that they do not meet the requirements of a definition. Thus, on the pretense of determining what virtue is, Socrates actually pursues the prior project of showing what fundamental virtue is not. What is really accomplished in the Meno is not a theory about virtue but rather a theory about what is necessary to frame a good theory about virtue. The first such necessity is attention to what is truly universal about 'virtue.
' Meno's most common error involves naming various examples of virtue instead of naming what is common to all the examples. A closely related necessity for a definition is that it cannot use the term to be defined within the definition itself. Socrates makes this point in the context of Meno's idea that virtue is the ability to acquire beautiful things. Socrates makes Meno admit that such acquisition is virtuous only if it is just. But if justice is a virtue, it cannot be used in the definition of virtue (i. e., Meno has basically defined virtue as the acquisition of beautiful things in the context of a type of virtue).
This is truly an awesome project -- Socrates (and Plato after him) is trying to convince a world that has always been confident in its knowledge that it in fact knows nothing about the things of which it is most certain. What is even more striking is that he is trying to convince the world not only that it does not know, but also that it does not even know how to know. Socrates makes no claim to know the real answer to the question of virtue, but he does claim to know the basic form that such an answer would take. Nonetheless, this radical destabilization of everybody's most heartfelt knowledge about goodness is a painful and disorienting process for Socrates' interlocutors, who are repeatedly flabbergasted by what they now seem not to know.
This uncertainty comes to a head in the paradox about seeking what one does not know, which Meno brings up after one of Socrates' unforgiving deconstructions. How are we to look for virtue without first knowing what it looks like? This question inspires Socrates to introduce an early version of his idea of anamnesis -- the idea that learning truth is really a matter of the soul recollecting what it has learned before its current human birth. This idea has always been a major focal point for readers of Plato, partly because it seems to be a radical departure from Socrates' constant claims that he knows he knows nothing.
The theory of anamnesis seems to be a glaringly positive piece of theory amongst a heap of negatives and deconstructions. In the end, Socrates has in fact made a few substantive points about virtue besides the point that to learn it (if it were knowledge) would actually be to recall it. The most important such point is that the good or virtuous depends on wisdom: 'All that the soul undertakes and endures, if directed by wisdom, ends in happiness. ' This will be a recurring theme in the rest of Plato's work -- true virtue is not a matter of custom, but rather of knowledge.
In the Meno, however, this is not stated clearly. There is a lingering conflict between the conclusion that virtue is, 'as a whole or in part,' a kind of wisdom and the conclusion that no one can teach it (so that it cannot be knowledge). The Meno leaves us hanging between defining virtue as straight knowledge or as a kind of mysterious wisdom revealed to us by the gods 'without understanding. ' It is seen as likely that most virtuous men are so by holding 'right opinions' rather than true knowledge. Right opinions lead us to the same ends as knowledge, but do not stay with us because they are not 'tied down' by an account of why they are right. Thus, we can only depend on semi-divine inspiration to keep us focused on right opinions rather than wrong ones.
This dilemma brings us back to Socrates' (and Plato's) original purpose -- the mode of dialogic analysis Socrates pursues with Meno is meant first of all to show up wrong opinions. Secondly, it is meant to clear the ground for an inversion of the whole sequence of right opinion and truth. If the requirements for a definition of virtue can be filled, we would no longer need to test out opinions blindly (as is done throughout the Meno). Rather, we would have an account of virtue first -- an idea of virtue that is 'tied down' -- and could determine the details from there.
The Meno only pursues the first part of this project, but it lays a great deal of groundwork for the second.